AS HIS CONFLICTS with the dominant forces within the Communist movement mounted, Sidney Hook put the finishing touches on Towards the Understanding of Karl Marx: A Revolutionary Interpretation (1933), a masterful examination that even today remains one of the most compelling guides to Marx’s thought. The book took germinal form in some of Hook’s writings and talks of the late 1920s. It was, in finished form, his greatest accomplishment of the early 1930s.
The book’s release, timed to commemorate the fiftieth anniversary of Marx’s death, coincided with the "bank holiday" declared by President Franklin Delano Roosevelt in March 1933, a date which seemed to mark the nadir of capitalism’s basic financial institutions.
The premise of Towards the Understanding of Karl Marx was that Marxism "is not an armchair philosophy of retrospection, but a philosophy of social action; more specifically, a theory of social revolution."(1) Since Marx’s death, that understanding, Hook argued, had been buried beneath an accumulation of interpretations to the contrary. The first and most powerful half of Towards the Understanding of Karl Marx was devoted, hence, not to explicating Marx but to a critical history of his interpreters.
The eclipse of the active element in Marxist theory was due, Hook held, mainly to the rise of reformist Social Democracy in nineteenth-century Germany, a phenomenon which he explained by historical factors: Economically, Germany rose to imperialist stature, permitting state insurance and rising wages for skilled workers, and encouraging nationalism and conservative trade unionism; politically, the combined influence of Bismarckian repression and subsequent liberalization caused timidity among leading socialists, a penchant for restrained language and a desire to maintain electoral respectability.
The two wings of German Social Democracy – the "orthodoxy" of Karl Kautsky and Rudolph Hilferding, which held Marxism to be an objective science of social development proving the inevitability of socialism, and the "revisionism" of Edward Bernstein, who argued for abandoning talk of revolution altogether and declaring the party an association of democratic social reform – were in Hook’s judgment equally illegitimate claims to the tradition of Marx: "Instead of dialectical materialism, the German socialists became sensationalist and mechanical, ignoring praxis."(2) (9, 33)
Marxist orthodoxy between 1895 and 1917, Hook wrote, was "not only fatal to honest thinking; it involved the abandonment of the revolutionary standpoint which was central to Marx’s life and thought." His criticism of Marxism’s ossification within German Social Democracy and the falsity of the social-democratic claim to uphold Marx’s method was consistent with Georg Lukacs’ essays in History and Class Consciousness (1923), especially "What is Orthodox Marxism?" But Hook was even closer to Karl Korsch, whose Marxism and Philosophy? (1923) declined to compete for the mantle of "orthodoxy," renouncing the very impulse to orthodoxy as dogmatic and religious.(3)
Hook gave rather grudging credit to Lukacs for linking "Marx up – unfortunately much too closely – with the stream of classical German philosophy." Korsch had confirmed the "practical-historical axis of Marx’s thought," Hook wrote, though he had underestimated "the difficulties in treating the formal aspect of Marx’s thought from this point of view." (ix, xii)
Reformists seemed on surest footing in their claims to orthodoxy – that is, accurate representation of Marx – when citing certain phrases of Engels, Marx’s lifelong collaborator. But even Engels, Hook maintained, was not what German Social Democracy had made him out to be. In a series of late-life letters which Hook translated into English for the first time and appended to his book, Engels warned against fetishism of legality and crude economic determinism. The "orthodoxy" of Social Democracy, Hook concluded, was in reality based upon a highly selective reading of Engels.(4)
One contemporaneous challenge to Second International reformism came from French syndicalist Georges Sorel, who was appalled by parliamentary cooptation in France and trade union conservatism in Germany. Sorel, wrote Hook, repudiated the reformist fetishism of pacifism and celebrated direct mass action but fell prey to irrationalism and anti-intellectualism with a cult of "myth" that foresook rational politics.
Marxism’s real line of preservation lay elsewhere, in the theory and activism of Polish-German revolutionary Rosa Luxemburg and Russian Bolshevik leader V.I. Lenin. Both Luxemburg and Lenin had criticized social-democratic reformism, pressed for working-class self-emancipation, repudiated economism (the idea that workers left to their ordinary struggles over wages and conditions will automatically rise to revolution), and advocated that the seizure of political power be the aim of the socialist movement.
Whereas the German Social Democrats voted for war bonds, Luxemburg and Lenin argued for class struggle to defeat imperialism and war. Thus, as the leaders of the Second International proudly proclaimed their Marxist "orthodoxy," Luxemburg and Lenin and their sundry "deviations" had shown a greater fidelity to the revolutionary method of Marx and Engels.
Neither Luxemburg nor Lenin – the heroes of Hook’s book – passed without criticism. On the famous point of dispute between the two over forms of socialist organization, Hook came down on Lenin’s side, judging tight discipline appropriate to Russia’s repressive conditions. Hook also dissented from Luxemburg on national liberation, challenging her theory that accumulation crisis would inexorably require imperialism’s collapse at its core.
As for Lenin, Hook resurrected his epistemological objections to the mechanical materialism of Lenin’s Materialism and Empirio-Criticism. In contrast to some of his writings of the 1920s, however, Hook was appreciative of Lenin’s general intellectual contributions, esecially the emphasis upon revolutionary practice in What Is to Be Done? In that call to action, Hook maintained, lay Lenin’s "true philosophy," that which he actually had to follow in order to bring about the Soviet revolution. Hook went so far as to praise Lenin as the only accurate interpreter of Marx. (62-64)
Mistaken interpretations of Marx, Hook argued, depended upon the extraction of his statements from their polemical context. Only a historical reading of Marx, one that positioned him in relation to the doctrines he sought to refute, would reveal his method. What seems wildly contradictory in Marx – here incitement to voluntary action, there an emphasis on unalterable economic causality – becomes "the application of the same principles and purposes to different historical situations," if grasped contextually. (67)
Another frequent mistake, Hook wrote, was to seek in Marx’s writings an absolute law or pure science: "Social science is class science; and what Marx means by science is not what is meant by the word today, but criticism based upon the observable tendencies of social development." Because revolutionary commitment infused all of Marx’s theory, the search for an objective Marxist science outside of class struggle would end in frustration or distortion. (69)
At the core of Marx’s thinking was his dialectical method, which Hook argued had a number of exceptional characteristics: an historical and materialist basis, unlike Hegel’s idealist abstraction; an insistence on cultural interconnectedness without any single explanatory principle; an admission of the interrelation of cause and effect, so that consciousness was not simply effect and the external world not merely causal; and the realization that social change occurs through a combination of social conditions, felt needs, and action.
Although Marx carried over from Hegel the dialectical understanding that change involves unity through preservation, difference in destruction, and qualitative novelty, Marx did not, according to Hook, take dialectics to mean an abstract triadic model capable of mechanical application to any social process. Marx merely took from idealism the insight that knowledge is active and that sensations are social, not mere biological impressions on passive subjects.
The significance of Marx’s method was not its abstract character, as so many mistakenly supposed, but its practical implications. Proper dialectical understanding, Hook explained, illuminates the path between and beyond reform and utopia. Reformers try to mediate irreconcilables, utopians to suppress cultural and economic continuities. Each meets with futility. Revolutionary socialism, by contrast, pursues sweeping social transformation while simultaneously proposing to build from what exists.
Marxism draws upon the visionary qualities of utopianism as well as the practicality of the reform impulse, while refusing either to draw up fixed blueprints of the new social order or to capitulate to contemporary political situations. "Marxism," Hook concluded, "is neither a science nor a myth, but a realistic method of social action." (114)
Towards the Understanding of Karl Marx received a wide audience and high praise from reviewers. In The Nation, independent radical Benjamin Stolberg pronounced the book "the most significant contribution to Marxism which has as yet appeared in America" and gushed that "it is thrilling to behold such intellectual courage in a university teacher." In The New Republic, the British scholar of politics Harold J. Laski called Towards the Understanding of Karl Marx "the most stimulating introduction" to Marx "so far written in English."(5)
Along with the praise came a telling line of criticism. Although Hook had not explicitly sought to reconcile pragmatism and Marxism in his book, he was faulted for mixing the two doctrines. Hook had in fact been the favorite student of John Dewey, the most important pragmatist philosopher of the twentieth century. Accusations that he was attempting to import Dewey into Marx were probably made with knowledge of that connection.
Beliefs are rules for action, the pragmatist theory of inquiry argues, and thinking is the production of habits for action. Our conception of an object, according to pragmatists, is determined by our understanding of its potential effects. The coherence of any idea is insufficient to judge the idea’s veracity or "warranted assertibility" (the substitute term for truth that Dewey came to prefer because of its less absolutist connotations).
Ideas must be verifiable in experience. Dewey, in fact, preferred the term "experimentalism" over "instrumentalism" or "pragmatism" to describe his philosophy.
This extension of basic scientific method into the realm of social and moral life Dewey distinguished from preceding empiricisms because of its emphasis upon creative thought in the generation of knowledge. Pragmatists contend that people are not mere creatures of physical or spiritual forces. Humans anticipate and aim toward – and thereby shape, to one degree or another – future outcomes.
Since future consequences cannot always be foreseen, pragmatism requires that all propositions be treated as hypothetical, fallible, and provisional. At the same time, classical pragmatists refuse to condone cynicism, skepticism, and nihilism and strive to enhance self-critical intelligence and expand democracy.(6)
Although Dewey’s name had not appeared once in the entire text of Towards the Understanding of Karl Marx, both Laski and Stolberg perceived his undue influence. "By using ... characteristically pragmatic terms in all their technical implications," wrote Stolberg, "Dr. Hook persuades himself that Marx was a sort of left-wing, revolutionary Dewey. The truth is that both the Marxian epistemology and its psychology are the exact opposite....Marxian `instrumentalism’ has none of the worship of empiricism of the pragmatists. It is calculated to advance revolutionary tactics within a strictly a priori social logic. It learns from means only when they are conceived to serve its ends, while pragmatism is the idolatry of endless means. Pragmatism, indeed, is the most sophisticated expression of the planlessness of modern capitalism."(7)
Stolberg was correct about the pragmatist undercurrents of Towards the Understanding of Karl Marx. But in reproducing the left’s conventional biases against pragmatism, he failed to engage Hook’s arguments. He omitted, for example, Hook’s pragmatist reading of Marx’s theses on Feuerbach, which Hook astutely took to mean, "Any problem which cannot be solved by some actual or possible practice may be dismissed as no genuine problem at all." (76)
In linking pragmatism to capitalism, Stolberg simply could not admit to the possibility of the revolutionary socialist pragmatism conceived by Hook. "The task of the revolutionary philosopher," Hook had written, "is to bring social classes to an awareness of what it is they are doing and of the historical conditions of their activity." (185)
By associating pragmatism with capitalism even in a text that held as its explicit principle the abolition of capitalism, Stolberg had substituted intellectual prejudice for argument. Stolberg’s Nation review was nevertheless representative of the fate Hook’s project would so often meet on the left, despite widespread recognition of his lucidity and scholarship.(8)
The leaders of the Communist Party were unable to temper their criticism, as Stolberg did, with appreciation of Hook’s achievement. Their vitriol was peculiar, since Towards the Understanding of Karl Marx did not once polemicize against the Marxism of the Comintern or express any qualms about developments in the Soviet Union since 1917.(9) Hook’s salute to Lenin and the Third International as the rescuers of Marx from reformism was a fact that did not escape the book’s reviewers. "To Dr. Hook," wrote Stolberg, "it is Lenin who is the greatest Marxian revolutionary, not merely tactically but also dialectically."(10)
Nonetheless, Towards the Understanding of Karl Marx was sure to provoke Communist misgivings. Hook endorsed dialectical materialism in a form incompatible with that doctrine as it was coming to be defined by the Communist Party. Communist theoreticians increasingly treated Marxism as an infallible science capable of revealing absolute historical laws, presented the dialectic as a tripartite formula of thesis-antithesis-synthesis, and treated culture as a secondary sphere fundamentally determined by an economic base.(11)
By challenging Communism to abandon such narrow formulations, by arguing that this sort of philosophical dogma had nothing in common with Marx, by criticizing Russian masters like Georgi Plekhanov and Nikolai Bukharin for their monistic simplification, by expressing debt to the heretics Lukacs and Korsch, Hook had not merely pushed philosophical boundaries. He had overstepped them.
Had Hook’s sole difference with the Communist Party been its Third Period program, he might have been able to sustain a relationship of critical sympathy with the party, for soon after the German disaster the CP began to advocate a "united front from below" – a stunted form of the united front in which party members tried to persuade rank-and-file socialists to join them in common action while still denouncing socialist leaders in emphatic terms.
The Comintern’s sectarianism and contribution to the Nazi seizure of power, however, were only one issue in Hook’s rupture with the American Communist Party. A sustained attack on his own writings, immediately after the 1932 election had concluded, was more important. Although Towards the Understanding of Karl Marx had not yet appeared in print, Hook had completed the manuscript and had since 1930 been publishing articles enunciating its themes. When vilification of Hook erupted in the party press just prior to the publication of Towards the Understanding of Karl Marx, it was clear that the party was preparing in advance for the book’s appearance.
Late in 1932, Hook received a telephone call from Joseph Freeman. Freeman invited him to a meeting with top party officials to discuss his views on Marxism. Rumors had been circulating that the party wanted to recruit Hook, perhaps because of his status as an authority on Marx, perhaps in order to utilize his connections to win over Dewey. But when Hook reached the ninth floor of party headquarters on East 13th Street, he found that the meeting had quite a different purpose.
Hook was directed to a table at which sat the party’s highest leaders, including Earl Browder, Clarence Hathaway, James Ford, Alexander Trachtenberg, Sam Don, Avram Landy, Joseph Pass, Joseph Freeman, Robert Minor and V.J. Jerome. Browder requested a summary of his forthcoming book and Hook delivered it. Then Sam Don – a graduate of the Lenin School in Moscow who served for years on the staff of The Daily Worker – argued adamantly against Hook, claiming that Hook’s arguments for the primacy of historical process rather than physical matter were idealist and citing a number of passages from Engels to prove it.
Hook responded that because revolutionaries seek to create a new society different from existing reality, the mirror theory of consciousness was inadequate; a copy-book theory of knowledge could not account for anticipation, let alone imagination.
The argument, which lasted over an hour, also touched upon Hook’s disparagement of universal laws of social development, his views on dialectics, and his doubt that Marx meant the "inevitability" of communism to be taken literally. Trachtenberg, Freeman and Browder appeared to Hook to be fairly receptive to his arguments, except on the question of the dialectic, which Hook interpreted simply as the element of conscious activity in human action and did not believe extended to nature itself.
Browder asked Hook how he then differed from Max Eastman, a figure scorned by the party in part for his own renunciations of the dialectical theory of nature. Hook recounted his severe criticisms of Eastman’s attack on dialectics and conception of revolution as social engineering.
Party leaders also appeared discomfited by Hook’s assertion of the relative autonomy of politics and philosophy. Hook explained his view that dialectical materialism or any other metaphysical position did not necessarily entail any specific set of social beliefs, so that one could be a communist or socialist and not a dialectical materialist, or a materialist without espousing socialism.
After the meeting ended, with Hook having provided his answer to each criticism leveled against his work, he and Browder retired for a cup of coffee to a cafeteria on University Place, where Browder complained to Hook about the chaos caused to the party in 1929 by the departure of the Lovestone group.(12)
Although Hook had answered his opponents, he had not dissuaded them. Hook’s most persistent antagonist during the meeting, Sam Don, was at that time, unbeknownst to Hook, a critic of Browder’s conciliatory gestures toward "bourgeois intellectuals." Former Daily Worker correspondent Sender Garlin describes Don as a "literal-minded kind of fundamentalist," and Don proved true to that reputation in his volley against Hook in a Daily Worker article on December 14, 1932.
Don castigated Hook and even upbraided the party’s theoretical magazine, The Communist, for having not yet attacked Hook’s "scholastic and absolute revisionism." This scorcher made Hook the first intellectual supporter of Foster and Ford to come under party fire.(13) The January 1933 issue of The Communist, as if in answer to Don’s cue, unveiled a condemnation of Hook by V.J. Jerome, "Unmasking an American Revisionist of Marxism."
Although he had clearly sided with Don during the ninth-floor meeting, Jerome, who had audited a course of Hook’s at NYU in 1930-31, had refrained from saying much in the course of the debate. His article was crude and tendentious. Jerome ignored Hook’s admiration for Marx and Lenin and his repeated criticisms of the social-democratic views of Bernstein, Kautsky and Hilferding, baselessly imputing to Hook the view that "not in Marx, not in Lenin, nowhere except in German revisionism can Hook find the true Marxism!"
Jerome accused Hook of being "a willful distorter and falsifier of Marxism," and maintained that Hook’s "pluralistic hypotheses are a return from scientific militant materialism to reactionary idealist experientialism." He dismissed Hook’s polemics against Max Eastman as quarrels within the same bourgeois family, and linked both Hook and Eastman by their association with Dewey, whom Jerome described ad hominem as "this American bourgeois in cap and gown" and "a blatant supporter of the social-fascist presidential candidate, Norman Thomas!" The fact that Hook, in contrast to Dewey, had thrown his public support behind the Communist slate was conveniently suppressed.
Jerome blustered that "with Hook the speaker for the proletarian platform has come Hook the ideologist of the platform for the bourgeoisie, Hook the carrier of the specific philosophy of the American bourgeoisie dressed in phrases of Marxism." In a final triumph of Third Period logic, Jerome proclaimed that "despite his objective position among the intellectuals uniting toward the revolutionary movement, Hook is subjectively a force pulling away from it."(14)
The attack did not impress radical intellectuals. Not even those who were themselves critical of Hook’s pragmatism found Jerome’s approach productive. Rather than stigmatize Hook, Jerome’s hatchet job reinforced the convictions of many who already held the Communist Party’s theoretical and political approach hapless.
J.B.S. Hardman, editor of a trade union publication, The Advance, wrote to Hook that, "If the job had not been done so clumsily and to a considerable degree dishonestly, I should not like to take exception to it, for the `revision’ is there. The trouble with professional and labeled Marxians is that they neither know Marx nor care to know him; if anybody isn’t going about the matter religiously he is their enemy entirely. They only feel safe in an atmosphere of faith. Then they know how to exact it and how to break it."(15)
Jerome’s blast failed even to satisfy those intellectuals who remained dedicated Communists. New Masses editor Granville Hicks wrote to Hook that "it ought to be possible to criticize a man’s ideas without calling him a social-fascist," and confessed that, "Personally I cannot accept your instrumentalism, and I should have welcomed an intelligent analysis of it. But Jerome’s article is practically worthless."(16)
Even at the late date of September 1933, Smith College professor Newton Arvin wrote Hook that he had greatly enjoyed Towards the Understanding of Karl Marx: "I don’t know what the official Party attitude toward it is (though I suppose it is unfavorable), but if you are still proscribed as a heretic, I fear that I am one, too, for I haven’t succeeded in seeing anything that, in my ignorance perhaps, strikes me as wrong with it."(17)
The smear campaign against Hook did not abate, however. In January 1933, the Daily Worker unleashed a wave of invective against him. One article described approvingly the disruption by hecklers of a teachers’ meeting at which Hook and his old City College professor Harry Overstreet spoke.(18)
In another Daily Worker polemic, H.M. Wicks – a "master of vituperation," as one former Communist who knew him recalls – purported to explain "how Hook serves capitalists." After calling Hook a "shallow vulgarizer," "muddled pretender" and "philosophic hack," Wicks alleged that Hook had been privately telling "those who will listen that no one in the Communist Party, U.S.A. or in the Communist Party of the Soviet Union knows the first thing about philosophy."(19)
In February and March, The Communist published Hook’s reply to Jerome, which Hook had shared with Arvin, Hicks, and Corliss Lamont prior to publication.(20) The move was highly unusual for a journal devoted to laying down uniformly correct positions, since it admitted implicitly the value of exchange over fundamental differences within Marxism. Rather than simply produce Hook’s reply, however, The Communist printed it within a two-part article by party leader Earl Browder, sandwiching long passages from Hook’s response betwixt Browder’s point-by-point rebuttal.
Jerome and Wicks came in for some criticism from Browder for the clumsy manner in which they had carried out their attacks, but Browder came down on their side on the general charge that Hook had "an understanding of Marxism in conflict with that of the Communist Party and the Communist International." Hook began his rebuttal to Jerome with quotations from Marx, Lenin, even Stalin – this was the first and only time that Hook would summon Stalin as a positive authority in defense of a position – meant to demonstrate that each rejected dogmatism.
Hook justly accused Jerome of "intellectual dishonesty" for misrepresenting his position and called for a "creative Marxism" rather than one based upon sacred texts. "The teachings of Marx, Engels and Lenin are the most valuable truths we have ... . But they themselves have urged that any movement which refuses to learn new things in new situations – to submit all principles to the test of experience and action – is doomed to sectarianism and futile failure."
Browder, however, accused Hook of arrogance in presuming that he, and not the Communist parties of the world, understood Marxism properly. Hook’s philosophy, Browder concluded, was idealist, so that "while it puts on a brave revolutionary face as emphasizing action, more action, [it] achieves the opposite result in reality by laying the foundation for confusion and disruption."(21)
Before the exchange, Hook harbored hopes that Browder would come to his defense, though in a letter to Will Herberg he lamented "illiterate party bureaucrats like Jerome and Don and Wicks, [who] attempt to settle things merely by quotation." With the mutilation of his reply to Jerome in The Communist and Browder’s refutation, it was clear that Hook could expect no redemption from on high.
"What a piece of work," wrote Herberg.
"Are you satisfied now that you can expect nothing from Browder? Browder not only endorses all of Jerome’s lies and outright forgeries but even ’blames’ Jerome for not going far enough: ’Jerome’s crime in this respect is serious because he thereby detracted slightly from the full force of his attack against Hook’s revisionism.’ In my opinion, Browder’s article is even more ignorant and even more indecent, if that is possible, than Jerome’s.
Morris U. Schappes concurred: "Well, Browder is as bad as Jerome, and he doesn’t seem able to learn from your demonstration of Jerome’s blunders."(22)
By late spring 1933, Hook and the Communist Party were completely estranged. Hook’s philosophical convictions ran too deep to permit him to capitulate to party authority, as Browder insisted. Precisely because he remained a communist and revolutionary Marxist, Hook was unable to submit to the authoritarian and monolithic form of discipline that had been demanded from him by the Communist Party.
The onslaught against Hook’s Marxism by party officials had only given urgency to a differentiation long in the making. Hook’s pragmatism had given to his Marxism a methodological emphasis upon provisional truth rather than absolute certainty, scientific inquiry over doctrinaire fidelity, flux and change over fixity and determinism, and the potential of human action over fatalism. Although Hook did not deny the importance of theoretical works and historical conditioning, he sought to restore the active and subjective component of Marxism against the hardened Marxism propounded by the Second International.
While occasionally critical of official Communism, Hook had been a dedicated fellow-traveler and political supporter of the Communist Party. His criticisms derived not from a hostility to communism as a principle and social goal, but from the perception that official Communism was straying from its stated aim and classical theory.
Intellectual historian Morton White once wrote that John Dewey had led a "revolt against formalism" in philosophy.(23) Likewise, Hook helped to initiate a revolt against formalism within American Marxism. The formalists, typified by Jerome, Wicks, Don and Browder, temporarily crushed his revolt. Unwittingly they had driven him to revolution.
Hook had sought to refute the copy-book materialism of Lenin in Materialism and Empirio-Criticism, but only so as to make sense of the revolutionary activism of the Lenin of What Is to Be Done? Now, it appeared, Lenin and the rest of the revolutionary tradition required rescue from the Communists.
ATC 68, May-June 1997
Solidarity 3 weeks 10 hours